|
in Mental Disability Evaluation |
|
A much shorter version of this 64-page, much revised, much updated, unpublished paper was published in 1994 as Observations on Disability Evaluation in the Social Security Administration. That version touches on, but does not focus on, evaluation of mental disability, which this paper examines at much greater length. Preliminary versions were presented at the First Biennial Conference on Community Research and Action, University of South Carolina, Columbia, South Carolina, May, 1987 and the 96th Annual Convention of the American Psychological Association, Atlanta, Georgia, August 1988. There's more background about my own SSA work history on the page summarizing the published article. I haven't kept up with Social Security developments in any depth, but from time to time I notice that not much has changed. Here's a recent opinion column. This paper is often the most-looked-at page on my website. SSA is still messing with people's lives. |
Ideological assumptions underlying the Social Security Administration's disability adjudication process are fundamentally at odds with the reality of bureaucratic decisionmaking. SSA insists that objective decisionmaking can be ensured by a variety of managerial procedures. However, the notion that disability is objectively determinable has been questioned on theoretical grounds. Even if disability were objectively determinable in theory, actual bureaucratic reality makes such objectivity unlikely to be attained in practice. The conflict between ideology and reality is seen most clearly in the necessarily subjective evaluation of mental disability.
One of the central tasks of the Social Security Administration (SSA) is to provide financial support to disabled individuals in accordance with legislative mandates, primarily through the Social Security Disability Insurance (SSDI) and Supplemental Security Income (SSI) programs. Legislators and SSA policymakers assume that the equitable and efficient disbursement of disability benefits is a difficult but attainable goal, with nothing inherently impossible about objective, consistent claims adjudication. Thus, the challenge as defined by agency ideology is to tighten internal controls and to minimize discretionary action by individual bureaucrats who merely should apply standardized rules in an evenhanded fashion. The degree to which this challenge is met is evaluated continually by SSA and periodically by other agencies of the government (e.g., General Accounting Office, 1986, 1987, 1989a, 1989b).
The particular ideological defense of SSA's disability programs is not surprising. It parallels defenses of SSA's retirement program and, indeed, it parallels defenses of programs across the entire range of administrative agencies. The generalized assumption is that, if rules are clear and management does its job, individual bureaucrats can perform reasonably consistently and accurately. This assumption may in fact be justified in programs such as SSA's age-based retirement system or the local motor vehicle registration bureau, though even relatively straight-forward programs such as these can become bureaucratic morasses. Still, although all bureaucracies have certain frustrating similarities, obtaining a license plate rarely reaches the complexity of demonstrating that one is disabled. Much of that complexity results from a key fact that calls into question the underlying objectivity assumption: In reality, "disability" essentially is a subjective state of being that defies rationalized systematic adjudication (Stone, 1984).
The subjective nature of disability, and the consequences of that subjectivity for SSA claims adjudication, have been examined in detail (Bloch, 1992; Cofer, 1985, 1987; Diehl, 1990; Dixon, 1973; Liebman, 1976, 1985; Mashaw, 1983; Mashaw et al., 1978; Mezey, 1988; Stone, 1984; Taibi, 1990; Weaver, 1989). The most subjective area of disability adjudication, however--the evaluation of mental disability--has been relatively neglected by academic observers, despite increasing attention by advocates for the mentally disordered (Rubenstein, 1985, 1986), by professional practitioners (Anthony & Jansen, 1984; Novack, 1987; Novack & Bernard, 1985), by SSA itself (Collins & Erfle, 1985), and by other government agencies (General Accounting Office, 1986). Since there is little support for SSA's assumption that even physical disability can be evaluated objectively, the identical assumption about mental disability makes the shortcomings of SSA's ideology readily apparent. For despite important recent reforms in the evaluation of mental impairments, SSA continues insufficiently to take into account theoretical and practical differences between mental and physical disability when it insists that both can be evaluated by similar criteria.
For mentally disordered people, dealing with SSA's objectivity requirements is often the only way to obtain money for rent, food, and other necessities. SSA provides the "largest pot of money available to mentally disabled people outside the state hospital budget" (Rubenstein, 1986, p. 390). Unfortunately, "bureaucracies like the Social Security Administration and welfare agencies can frustrate the average individual; for patients with severe psychiatric impairment, such bureaucracies may seem overwhelming. Therefore these individuals are frequently deprived of the sparse community resources that are available" (Lipton, Sabatini, & Katz, 1983, p. 821). Widespread publicity about the tens of thousands of mentally disabled individuals whose SSI and SSDI benefits were abruptly terminated in the early 1980s graphically illustrated SSA's impact on people whose very impairments make it difficult to adapt to complex bureaucratic requirements (General Accounting Office, 1986; Rubenstein, 1985). Current concern about the large proportion of homeless individuals with mental disorders demonstrates that this problem has not been resolved (Diehl, 1990).
It is somehow fitting to discover that Franz Kafka learned about "Kafkaesque" bureaucratic meaninglessness while working in a disability benefits agency (Mashaw, 1983, p. 91, footnote 9). Like Kafka, I too worked within the disability system, for two and a half years as a claims representative, or interviewer-adjudicator, in three SSA district offices and for eight months as a vocational-disability examiner in an SSA-affiliated state Disability Determination Service (DDS). As a bureaucrat, I was particularly intrigued by the inevitable disparity between governmental ideology and everyday bureaucratic reality, a disparity with serious consequences both for disabled claimants--especially the mentally disabled--and for SSA and DDS employees. My experiences in the agency have since led me to speculate about the bureaucratic context within which disability evaluation occurs. These speculations are at least tentatively confirmed by informal interviews with SSA bureaucrats at both the local and central policymaking level, with DDS examiners, doctors, and managers, and with attorneys and other advocates for the mentally disordered.
Explicitly or implicitly, every disability bureaucracy faces certain key issues, some of them perhaps unresolvable, as it attempts to develop a coherent approach to its policy mission (see, especially, Mashaw, 1983; Stone, 1984). Of particular relevance to adjudicating claims on the basis of mental disability are three interrelated problems that reflect the inadequacies of the basic objectivity assumption: (a) the interaction between individual bureaucrats and the larger bureaucracy; (b) the inevitable presence of inconsistent claims dispositions; and (c) the theoretical and practical conflicts among medical, legal, and bureaucratic assumptions in evaluating disability. Before directly turning to these three areas, some comments are in order about the origin and scope of SSA's disability system in general and the evaluation of mental impairment claims in particular.
Although SSA's disability programs now comprise "the largest system of administrative adjudication in the Western world" (Liebman, 1985, p. 1), with about 1,250,000 mental and physical disability claims filed each year, the United States was actually the last of the industrialized states to provide such benefits (Stone, 1984, p. 68). When the SSA retirement system was introduced in 1935 as part of the New Deal, Congress explicitly rejected the inclusion of disability. As might be expected, providing retirement benefits was itself not free of intense controversy and organizational complexity, and recent treatments of political and ideological factors in SSA's formative years continue to reflect disparate interpretations (Achenbaum, 1986; Cates, 1983; Derthick, 1979, 1990; Meyer & Wolff, 1993; Mezey, 1989). It was clear at the very beginning, however, that although allocating benefits to "entitled" workers older than the legal retirement age would present bureaucratic challenges, such problems would be minor when compared with the difficulties of allocating benefits to people who were "too disabled" to work.
As Congress considered proposals to establish disability benefits, "the definition of disability and the mode of determination in individual cases were at the heart of the controversy" (Stone, 1984, p. 69). Efforts were made to define disability precisely and narrowly so that decisions could be made objectively and also, importantly, so that costs could be prevented from escalating as rapidly as had occurred in disability programs in other countries and under private insurance plans in this country. The original Social Security Board finally urged a disability program in 1943. Three years later, it proposed defining a "permanent and total disability" as "any disability which is medically demonstrable by objective tests, which prevents the worker from performing any substantially gainful activity, and which is likely to be of long and continued duration" (Stone, 1984, p. 79).
Throughout the 1940s and 1950s, a disability program was strongly backed by the labor movement as well as by SSA itself. It was opposed by the insurance industry, the Chamber of Commerce, and the American Medical Association for a variety of economic, political, and technical reasons. These reasons went beyond conservative antipathy to any expanded federal function and suspicion of "socialized medicine" to include the view, expressed by physicians repeatedly in Congressional testimony, that proposed definitions of disability stressing medical objectivity were inadequate. Doctors argued that
disability determination is inherently subjective, and that honest physicians could legitimately disagree about whether a person is disabled. Many argued that medical science is incapable of determining whether people can or cannot work. Over and over again they told Congress that "medicine is not an exact science," and that disability is a social and psychological problem not amenable to exact definition by physicians. (Stone, 1984, p. 80)
Despite such widespread criticism, "nothing could shake Congressional belief in the ability of the medical profession to make reasonably accurate judgments of disability" (Stone, 1984, p. 83). When SSDI was finally enacted in 1956, as a limited program of early retirement benefits for insured workers at least 50 years old who had demonstrated significant recent work activity, disability was to be "objectively determined by medical examination or tests" and would not be based on "purely subjective symptoms" (Stone, 1984, p. 79). And to allay fears of federal expansionism and socialized medicine, the actual determination of disability would be made not by SSA but by individual state vocational rehabilitation agencies working under federal guidelines. However, apparently as a concession to physicians' objections that determining disability was not a medical responsibility, the final disability decision would be made not by a doctor but by a vocational specialist in the state agency who would take into account not only medical reports but social and vocational factors as well (Stone, 1984, p. 84). In essence, disability was officially viewed as a legal or administrative category, not a medical category, in much the same way that the law treats insanity.
SSDI expanded incrementally under political and judicial pressures, as its opponents predicted it would (Derthick, 1979; Stone, 1984). In 1958, the recent-work requirement was liberalized and benefits were provided for dependents of disabled workers; in 1960, the age-50 requirement was eliminated; in 1965, the original requirement for the presence of an impairment expected either to result in death or to be of "long-continued and indefinite duration" was changed to one expected to lead to death or to last 12 months. Today, after almost four decades, changes continue. Most significantly for the mentally disordered was the Social Security Disability Benefits Reform Act of 1984 (Collins & Erfle, 1985, detail legislative maneuvering leading to the Act). SSA policies for evaluating both mental and physical disability remain controversial, resulting in frequent judicial involvement (Liebman, 1985; Mashaw, 1983; Rubenstein, 1985; Taibi, 1990).
In addition to overseeing the expansion of SSDI and other Title II programs, in 1974 SSA began administering the new Title XVI SSI program, which provides federal welfare benefits to the disabled, the aged, and the blind. SSDI, like the SSA retirement system, is technically an insurance program. Eligibility is determined in part by having worked enough years under covered employment. The benefit amount, based upon the amount of past earnings, is funded through a disability trust fund consisting of workers' FICA payroll withholding taxes, and receipt of SSDI is popularly seen as an earned right regardless of financial need. SSI, on the other hand, replaced the individual states' welfare programs for the aged and the long-term disabled. Instead of a prior-work requirement, there is a needs-based, or poverty, requirement, and SSI is funded by general tax revenues. Both programs use the same definition of disability.
Some bureaucracies are built upon a flawed foundation. No matter how a judge adjusts the process that the bureaucracy uses to make institutional decisions, the structure and mission of the agency will remain flawed. The Social Security disability program provides an example of such a flawed institution. (Taibi, 1990, pp. 914-915)
Given SSA's confused beginnings, organization, and goals, Taibi's (1990) assessment is not unreasonable.
Although claimants file for SSDI and SSI at a federal Social Security office, where work- and needs-related criteria are evaluated, the actual disability decision is made by the state Disability Determination Service, usually located within the state vocational rehabilitation agency. This presents the "unusual scenario of a state agency deciding who qualifies for federal benefits under a federal program, following federal regulations" (Liebman, 1985, p. 5). DDSs, whose employees are subject to differing state political pressures and to standards set by different federal courts, vary significantly in their interpretations of federal rules, as well as in hiring standards, salary levels, and specific claims processing procedures. The resulting variation in "adjudicatory culture" (Mashaw, 1983, p. 156) adds to wide variation in outcomes. Unsurprisingly, SSA continually seeks to enforce DDS conformity with centralized views of correctness, and proposals to change the fundamental federal-state relationship are periodically considered.
In theory, a disability determination is jointly made by a DDS doctor and a vocational-disability examiner. The doctor, who examines the written medical record gathered by the examiner but who does not see or talk to the claimant, rates the degree to which the claimant is impaired by an objectively determinable medical condition. If the impairment is severe enough to match the detailed descriptions of medical conditions that automatically are considered disabling, then the claimant is said to meet or equal the listings. In most cases, however, since the condition does not meet that stringent level, the doctor rates the claimant's residual functional capacity (RFC), the ability to perform particular physical or mental activities (such as lifting heavy objects or following simple instructions). Significantly, because disability officially is seen as a legal rather than a medical concept, the DDS doctor does not indicate in writing whether or not the claimant can work. That decision technically belongs to the examiner, who takes the doctor's RFC rating, considers it in light of relevant vocational factors, and determines whether the claimant can work either at his or her past job or at other jobs, in which case the claim is denied, or whether the claimant cannot work at all and is thus fully disabled (there is no partial disability under SSA). The doctor countersigns the examiner's final determination.
If DDS examiners in reality were the vocational experts envisioned by those who designed SSDI, then there might be some justification for considering the disability decision to be other than primarily medical. For the most part, however, in a departure from original legislative intent, examiners are not vocational experts; they receive no training in vocational counseling or job placement (Mashaw, 1983). Mashaw (1983) compared a DDS located in one state's Education Department, where examiners, atypically, are considered the equivalent of professional counselors and are required to work toward a master's degree, with one in a state Welfare Department, where "pay scales and entry-level qualifications are low" and where "the line examiners, to be uncharitable, seemed merely to prefer doing [SS]DI work to driving a taxi" (p. 161). In most states, examiners have college degrees but no particular relevant expertise. They undergo about two months of training, with as much emphasis on the clerical side of the job as on the medical and vocational "professional judgment" side. Most DDSs do have a vocational expert for consultation in complex cases, but such consultation is not routine.
As a result partly of the ingrained notion that disability is really a medical problem despite the official rationale to the contrary, and partly of the gap between doctors and examiners in outlook, training, and status, I suspect that the examiner's final disability decision is often little more than an affirmation of what he or she takes to be the doctor's unstated opinion. In the case of physical disability claims, this power imbalance is mitigated to a certain extent by a variety of bureaucratic procedures as well as by the comparatively quantifiable nature of physical illness. The examiner is aware of the imbalance, but at least has an understanding of how to affect the decision if he or she wants to do so. When evaluating mental disability claims, however, the imbalance is exacerbated by the nature of mental disorder.
In the case of most physical disabilities, for example, examiners do not "apply vocational factors" to RFC ratings in a vacuum. Instead, they use a standardized vocational grid that directs standardized decisions according to age, education, and work history (Mashaw, 1983; Stone, 1984). Experienced and conscientious examiners learn the allowable limits of fudging the boundaries between categories. In addition, "they generally know a startling array of medical and pharmacological facts and have a sufficiently low regard for the reliability of various types of medical findings that they are willing to exercise independent judgment" (Mashaw, 1983, p. 167). Examiners often understand the listings well enough to tell the doctor when an important piece of evidence has been overlooked or when another consultative exam should be ordered. They can choose to reschedule a missed exam rather than to deny the claim for failure to attend, and sometimes, despite a general rule against it, they can give a case to a doctor perceived to be especially sympathetic (Mashaw, 1983). Of course, as Mashaw (1983) wondered about examiner interest in influencing case outcomes, "how often will an individual examiner's desire to nonconform surface in a system that emphasizes and rewards objective findings and conformity to routine?" (p. 179). Rather than go out of their way, many examiners merely take the doctor's rating of impairment as given, find the appropriate place in the grid, and write down the decision. The crucial point, however, is that examiners working on a physical disability claim more often than not do understand what they are supposed to do, and the sympathetic examiner who does want to help individual claimants can often figure out which steps are most likely to be successful.
Decisionmaking problems which are troubling and unavoidable in the adjudication of physical disability claims are of even greater consequence in the evaluation of mental disability. Early recognition of the differences between the two was reflected in the 1938 Social Security Board's conclusion that mental disability "should be excluded" from any SSA program "because it would be too hard to determine" (Stone, 1984, p. 72). The very existence of mental "illness," of course, has been questioned on theoretical grounds (Szasz, 1974). Less theoretically, DDS psychiatrists, clinical psychologists, and examiners who see themselves as responsible for dispensing tax dollars more often expect the mentally disabled to "try" to work. This especially seems to be the case when the disability includes alcoholism or drug addiction, which many doctors and examiners simply do not think should be a consideration despite guidelines to the contrary. The fact that people are stigmatized more by mental impairments than by physical ones (Tringo, 1970) may reduce the sympathy that often makes the adjudicatory difference in close cases. In general, "habits of thought and policies derived from medical care often have different results when applied to mental health services" (Buck, 1982, p. 219).
To a greater extent than is the case for physical impairment, clinical experts routinely disagree about the diagnosis, treatment, and prognosis of mental disorders. Such disagreement affects the extent to which DDS psychiatrists and psychologists conclude that a particular claimant meets the listings (Rubenstein, 1985). However, although the evaluation of mental disability is much more subjective than the official ideology acknowledges, this subjectivity is obscured by the same combination of bureaucratic papershuffling, reassuring checklists, and agency jargon that is used with somewhat more justification for physical impairment. Just as in the case of physical disability, where the examiner is handed a doctor's RFC form specifying whether the impairment allows heavy, medium, light, or sedentary work, in mental disability claims the examiner also receives an RFC form where job-related mental activities are rated as markedly, moderately, or not significantly limited. Two important distinctions must be made, though.
For one thing, there is no vocational grid to help the examiner apply the appropriate vocational factors. There are, in fact, no universally recognized "appropriate" factors at all. Age, education, and work history are simply not that relevant to a mentally impaired individual's ability to work (Rubenstein, 1985). Consequently, the examiner must work with ambiguous, poorly defined vocational factors, a frustrating task at best. Inexperienced or uninterested examiners can muddle through this task simply by going along with whatever decision the psychiatrist or psychologist is hinting at--if the hint can be understood.
Unfortunately, unlike the case for physical disabilities, experienced and concerned examiners often are not much better off than inexperienced ones because of the second factor: examiners' poor understanding of mental disability. Examiners generally receive much more training in the physical listings and the vocational grid than in the mental listings. Although an experienced examiner often understands when the doctor has misread a blood test result or overlooked relevant reports, he or she generally has no idea at all what the psychiatrist or psychologist has taken--or is supposed to take--into account, and thus has little basis to question the mental impairment rating or RFC. As a consequence, the final decision reflects the doctor's influence much more than does a comparable physical disability decision. Considering the greater subjectivity and ambiguity of mental disability evaluation, the result of the disparity for the claimant is that the often liberalizing impact of sympathetic examiners is lessened as the case essentially is resolved by one person rather than by two.
A different set of problems relects the way in which mental disorder affects claimants' pursuit of their claims. Stuve (1986), after interviewing mental health and SSA workers, noted:
The very disability which entitles the CMI [Chronically Mentally Ill] to benefits also makes it very difficult for them to go through the steps necessary to obtain these benefits. The CMI generally lack social skills, are easily confused and frustrated, and can become anxious and frightened in new situations when they are without their normal supports. The SSA process requires them to effectively communicate their disability, to deal with a confusing and frustrating system, and to do this on the SSA's home field--without many of their normal supports. Is it any wonder that the stress of going through this process causes some CMI to simply abandon the process? (pp. 1-2).
Stuve pointed out that even getting to the SSA office to file a claim is difficult for mentally impaired individuals, who may not have family or friends to rely upon. Once there, "receptionists have discouraged some CMI from applying because their disability is not readily visible. The applications are long and confusing, and the CMI are unable to complete them on their own" (p. 4). "There were complaints that applicants are often required to sign blank release forms, without any knowledge of where these forms would be sent. This can be a problem for the paranoid applicant" (p. 4). Correspondence from SSA or the state DDS is often "very difficult for the CMI to understand" (p. 9). "Some CMI refuse to go see doctors, forget to show up for appointments, and/or are uncooperative with the consulting [medical] examiner" (p. 15).
Complicating matters, many mentally impaired claimants apply for benefits alleging physical rather than mental disability. They "may exaggerate work skills and job history in an attempt to appear 'normal'" and may "simply refuse to admit to a disability" (Stuve, 1986, p. 5). Adding to the DDS burden, many therapists do not submit complete reports, reflecting both the low fees paid for time-consuming written evaluations and the all-too-common view that "it is therapeutically harmful for a patient to be labeled as sick. . . . As one disability rights advocate has said, 'Psychiatrists are astonishingly insensitive to the therapeutic benefits of having an income'" (in Stone, 1984, p. 223, footnote 22).
When the initial claim is denied, mentally disabled claimants "will need someone to help them through [the] appeals process. Even with help, many will find the appeal frustrating and anxiety provoking. . . . Some will simply give up and quit" (Stuve, 1986, p. 6). In a typical year, DDSs deny about two-thirds of all disability claims and even more reconsiderations. At the hearing level, however, "semiindependent" administrative law judges (ALJs) reverse DDS denials over 60 percent of the time(GAO, 1989a). Of the large minority whose denials are affirmed by the ALJs, the SSA Appeals Council unsurprisingly affirms nine out of ten. But claimants who follow through to federal district court receive allowances more than a third of the time. Stone (1984), discussing the better-than-even odds of getting initial denials reversed further down the claims process, noted that "if individuals appeal their cases, if they push against the boundaries with any energy at all, they stand a reasonable chance of getting through" (p. 161; see also Taibi, 1990). Mashaw (1983) pointed out that this "perseverence bounty," though important for those who attain it, "disadvantages the ignorant, the incompetent, and the demoralized" (p. 138). The mentally disordered are at least equally disadvantaged.
Adopted by Congress in response to widespread criticism of Administration efforts to cut the disability rolls, the 1984 Disability Amendments altered the rationale and specifics of the mental impairment listings and of DDS procedures for a three-year trial period ending in August, 1988. The changes were designed, in part, to increase the focus on work-related functional limitations and to move away from a reliance on one-shot evaluation of symptoms (Novack, 1987; Rubenstein, 1985; see also Collins & Erfle, 1985). The new emphasis grew out of a work group that consisted of representatives of SSA, the American Psychological Association, the American Psychiatric Association, the National Institute of Mental Health, the Mental Health Law Project, and others. Preliminary reports indicate that the new listings have indeed resulted in more allowances (Office of Assessment, 1987), and they generally are considered by advocates and practitioners to be a theoretical advance in the notion of mental disability (Novack, 1987; Rubenstein, 1985). In practice, however, they have not eliminated existing difficulties related to ambiguity, inconsistency, and bureaucratic power imbalances. The new approach, in fact, may have compounded these problems, particularly in view of SSA's grudging acceptance of the changes.
From my position as a DDS examiner, it seemed as if the new rules were often vague, the training inadequate, and the workloads unmanageable. Examiners, agency doctors, supervisors, and managers reacted in widely differing ways, clearly affecting case outcomes. The fate of an individual's claim increasingly seemed to depend on the particular examiner or doctor to whom it was assigned. Although not all DDS offices were affected to the same degree, many of these conditions were fairly widespread, particularly in more urbanized states. According to the General Accounting Office (GAO),
Examiners and DDS officials said that, because of increased emphasis on functional documentation and extensive forms to be filled out, the processing time for mental impairment cases under the new criteria was twice as great as for other disability cases. Their individual caseloads were running about 135 to 150 cases, they said, although they considered less than 100 to be a workable level. SSA has not established goals for pending case workloads. (1986, p. 14)
The GAO (1987) later reported that despite improvements in timeliness of SSA retirement claims, disability claims were taking longer to adjudicate that previously, a situation that has since worsened (Delfico, 1992). The delays apparently reflected, first, the chaos of the early Reagan-era mass benefit terminations; second, the initial impact of the new mental impairment listings; and third, continuing budget constraints and--significantly--continuing disagreement over how to evaluate disability (Delfico, 1992).
An internal SSA report (Office of Assessment, 1987) indicated significant problems with the bureaucratic response to the new listings. In general, although the national allowance rate was up, "substantial changes . . . occurred on the DDS level" (p. 3). In Massachusetts, the FY 1985 mental disability allowance rate of 58.5 percent rose to 73.7 percent in the last half of 1986. In Pennsylvania, by contrast, the initial 54.3 percent allowance rate actually dropped to 38.7 percent. "The wide fluctuations suggest that DDSs were not consistently applying the revised criteria" (p. 3). Moreover, DDS accuracy was found to be lower than previously. Significantly, "the decrease in accuracy is substantial among DDS mental disorder decisions which are unfavorable to the claimant" (p. 10). Despite these findings, however, within the SSA branch directly responsible for the disability program, inaccurate allowances resulting from alleged "overdevelopment" are seen as the problem, not inaccurate denials. SSA policymakers sought to lower the Massachusetts allowance rate rather than raise the Pennsylvania rate.
The purpose of focusing on work-related functional limitations in the new listings was to make it easier to allow claims that previously would have been denied. Not surprisingly, given Administration priorities, the mandated effort to broaden eligibility was linked to increasingly extensive case development and to a qualitatively different kind of file documentation. Unfortunately, these were changes that many examiners were poorly trained to handle and often resented. For example, examiners were uncomfortable with the new requirement to interview mentally impaired claimants or their relatives on the telephone in order to get a detailed description of daily activities and functional limitations. This task often seemed insurmountable to bureaucrats untrained in mental disorder, in intensive interviewing, or in detailed report writing. It was at first often simply ignored as caseloads expanded dramatically.
When the rules were further liberalized to make it possible to allow claims when the only impairment was alcoholism or drug addiction, the workload and resentment rose even more. Efforts in some states to solicit claims from mentally disordered homeless individuals added to the frustration, as homeless claimants were difficult to contact and often could provide little information about their medical history. Even examiners and doctors who were in agreement with the liberalized criteria became bogged down in mounting piles of folders. Despite resignations, a job freeze prevented hiring enough new examiners. More than a year after the implementation of the new listings, amid rumors of impending layoffs and vastly increased caseloads, a resolution was introduced in Congress "instructing the Social Security Administration not to increase the caseload of SSDI examiners or reduce the staff in state disability determination offices to levels that would prevent thorough, adequate case development" ("State Agencies," 1987).
Since the examiner decides how often to try to contact claimants, to reschedule missed exams, to write activities of daily living reports, and so on, a particular case outcome is strongly affected by the examiner's interest in pursuing it. Not surprisingly, many examiners, keeping in mind the quantitative nature of supervisory evaluations of their work, often are less interested in complete case development than in clearing as many "old" cases as possible. The perceived pressure, thus, despite official agency guidelines, is to deny claimants for failure to attend exams rather than to reschedule them, or to accept without question a doctor's nonlimiting RFC even if the examiner believes that more development will demonstrate that the claimant cannot work. Similarly, the primary concern of agency doctors sometimes seems to be to avoid being found "in error" by Quality Assurance. This, too, often results either in long delays in an effort to tie up all conceivable loose ends, or in denials that could have been allowances with more flexible case development and less rigid interpretation of the meant-to-be-liberal listings.
I have argued thus far that the differences between mental and physical impairments are not sufficiently taken into account by a bureaucratic ideology that insists both kinds of impairment can be evaluated on parallel objective grounds. This ideology conflicts with the greater subjective nature of diagnosing mental disorder. In addition, in the case of mental disability evaluation, the reality of bureaucratic administration raises to a greater magnitude the practical problems that are present to some degree even when evaluating physical impairments.
Referring to disability evaluation in general, Mashaw (1983) pointed out that
The subtle but powerful management actions that shape the adjudicatory culture--the focus of QA [Quality Assurance] review, the budget for CEs [Consultative Exams], the setting of productivity goals for examiners--have little obvious bearing on the outcome of particular cases, even though they may markedly affect the gross award or denial rates. (p. 187)
My suspicion is that the nature of mental disorder, and of people's knowledge of it and reaction to it, exacerbates such outcome effects significantly, particularly in view of several recurring, interrelated issues about which I will briefly speculate.
For present purposes, the interaction between individual bureaucrats and the larger bureaucracy can be thought of in three ways. First is the truism that the personal traits of individual bureaucrats differ. Although it can seek to hire and mold a particular kind of worker, the bureaucracy cannot eliminate variability in such factors as background, motivation, prejudices, politics, accuracy, analytical ability, and career goals (Mashaw, 1983). The inevitable case outcome effects should be especially strong in the evaluation of mental disability, which forces the observer to bring more of his or her own self to the evaluation process than is true for physical disability. The fact that many claims are reviewed for correctness cannot eliminate this problem, as reviewers similarly vary among themselves.
Second, and conversely, the nature of the bureaucratic situation imposes pressures that affect most of its members in similar ways. The overpowering quality of bureaucratic reality forces those who choose to remain in the system to conform to major system demands despite individual differences (Hummel, 1982). As job demands change in response to higher-level decisions--as, for example, decisions are made to increase or decrease the allowance rate for different categories of disability by enforcing certain rules or suspending others--the bureaucrat has little practical choice but to adapt, regardless of personal inclinations. The power of the situation may have a disproportionate impact on mental disability claims because there are more potentially reasonable ways to evaluate mental disability than is true for physical disability. The ideologically motivated selection of one particular method by policymakers, often in response to political decisions made outside the agency, may thus eliminate plausible alternatives more than is the case for physical disability.
The person and the situation interact in the third category, that of ideological differences concerning the very purpose of evaluating people for disability benefits. Although the bureaucracy decides who is disabled enough not to work, "enough" is neither self-evident nor stable over time. Discussing the origin of disability bureaucracies, for example, Stone (1984) detailed the close connection between disability and the labor market. The early English vagrancy laws, which made it illegal to give money to beggars who could work, were a response to the labor shortage caused by the Black Plague of 1347-49 (Stone, 1984, p. 34). The laws were designed to prevent workers from supporting themselves by begging while travelling in search of higher wages; only those legally recognized as unable to work were allowed to leave town.
With labor surplus rather than labor shortage, the trend in Western Europe "has been to extend eligibility under programs traditionally designed for the retired or the disabled as a way to alleviate unemployment" (Reno & Price, 1985, p. 24). It may not be a coincidence that, in contrast to the United States, "the most consistent trend [in Western Europe] is the apparent ease with which health and social security benefits are provided to those [mentally impaired individuals] who are in need" (Jansen, 1986, p. 1277). Even in the US, where a stricter social security program is conceived of as separate from the unemployment program and there has been resistance to officially linking the two (Reno & Price, 1985), there have been enough exceptions to make the inherent connection inescapeable. SSA's institution of early retirement benefits in 1961, during an economic recession, "was seen as a way to reduce unemployment among older workers. The change was in part a response to long-term technological unemployment, recognizing that persons who lost their jobs at older ages might never find other work" (Reno & Price, 1985, p. 30; see also Taibi, 1990). Similarly, changes in 1979 in SSA's vocational guidelines significantly eased the disability criteria for unskilled workers over age 50, making it possible for more older workers to drop out of the overcrowded work force (Stone, 1984, p. 165). As Stone noted,
When ideology mandates that everyone should work but society cannot provide employment for large segments of its population, the dilemma can be reconciled by defining a higher proportion of the population as disabled. Because disability is the most flexible of the categories of the need-based system, it is the one most readily available for use in this fashion. (p. 168)
The mental disability criteria are especially susceptible to changing economic, political, and professional pressures, as the mass eligibility terminations in the 1980s and the resulting new listings make clear (Rubenstein, 1985).
In addition to official views of where to draw the disability line, individual bureaucrats have their own ideas, which are often at odds with whatever official position is current. Although managers attempt to hire examiners and doctors who are not ideologically committed to stray outside the bounds of DDS acceptability, individual differences among DDS workers are common. This goes beyond personal sympathy for individual claimants seen as particularly deserving, and extends to explicit or implicit ideological positions that the rules are too strict or too lax. Some are perfectly willing to allow mental disability benefits even if the impairment can't be "objectively determined" because of a belief that "this person will never work" and that it doesn't really matter if support comes from SSA or unemployment or welfare, so long as it comes from somewhere. Others are extremely reluctant to allow claims for those who are seen as having "caused their own problems." Mental impairment claims raise these value issues more than do physical impairment claims.
In one typical study, the chances of two examiners reaching different decisions on sample cases were one in eight within the same DDS, and one in six for examiners in different DDSs (Stone, 1984, p. 133; see also General Accounting Office, 1987). Although such a level of inconsistency flies in the face of an objective bureaucratic approach, it should not be surprising given the inherently subjective nature of disability adjudication.
The disability decision process has been repeatedly studied and repeatedly criticized for (1) interstate inconsistency in both outputs (award rates) and inputs (use of CEs, for example); (2) dramatic variance between state agency-ALJ and ALJ-court decisionmaking; (3) ineffective QA control; and (4) the structural complexity and delay in the decision process. These same problems have been perceived ever since . . . 1960. Why, in twenty years, haven't some clear remedies emerged?
The answer lies in the elusiveness of accuracy in the DI . . . program. (Mashaw, 1983, p. 195)
Mashaw concluded that, in fact, bureaucratic inconsistency allows professional discretion to counter "a demand for objectivity [which], without changes in the resources devoted to processing, tends to produce stringency" (1983, p. 176). Thus, attempts to eliminate subjectivity reduce the allowance rate. Similarly, Stone (1984) argued that "a system of seemingly firm, objective standards . . . combined with a high degree of discretion on the part of disability determiners helps legislators resolve their ambiguity" (pp. 182-83). In this sense, inconsistency may be a way to enable the system to adapt to changing standards, but at the cost of an unknown number of people falling through the cracks. It might be better to openly acknowledge the subjective nature of disability adjudication--especially in the case of mental disability--and move away from a focus on centralized objective standards that cannot be met even in theory.
Adherence to objective scientific medical diagnosis fails on at least two counts. First, "medical criteria cannot be more objective and scientific than the body of knowledge and practice on which they rely" (Mashaw, 1983, p. 110). Many facts will always remain unknown to doctors and examiners, for reasons ranging from fragmentary medical records and individual differences in interpreting X-ray reports to bureaucratic preferences for certain kinds of information (such as the discounting of evidence submitted by chiropractors, social workers, and other "nonmedical" sources). In the case of mental impairments, where diagnosis is both difficult and subjective, "misdiagnosis is common" (Rubenstein, 1985, p. 720) and can directly affect whether or not a claimant meets the listings. This is doubly significant since, as discussed above, examiners are less able to use vocational factors to find someone disabled who does not meet the listings.
Second, there are individual differences in people's ability to function given the same degree of objective impairment.
That the clinical concept should fail as a restrictive mechanism is not surprising, because in an important way it sidesteps the key issue of disability: what is it that prevents people from working? In most instances, the cause is not some identifiable physical phenomenon but a complex set of interacting factors involving individual and family history, the state of the economy, and cultural and psychological as well as biological factors. . . . Pain, fatigue, shortness of breath--and, one might add, anxiety--are all real and very powerful subjective phenomena, but they defy measurement. (Stone, 1984, p. 134)
Such factors are all the more important--and more difficult to assess--in decisions to work or not to work made by the mentally impaired. The current mental listings do call for a greater focus on actual daily functioning. Still, it would not be surprising to find that agency psychiatrists and psychologists continue to rely more heavily on diagnosis and symptomatology than on laypersons' descriptions of daily functioning, despite abundant evidence that symptomatology and diagnosis bear little relation to the capacity to work (Anthony & Jansen, 1984).
The third general issue in disability evaluation has to do with the tension caused by the differing perspectives of doctors, lawyers, and bureaucrats. Mashaw (1983) discussed competing "justice models" within SSA, where bureaucratic rationality, professional treatment, and moral judgment provide clashing approaches to disability adjudication. "The bureaucratic rationality-moral judgment compromise was . . . struck, in part, in the form of a temporal separation--bureaucracy first, followed by individualized hearings for the dissatisfied" (p. 39). In the initial bureaucratic stages, there is a constant interplay between professional medical judgment and the bureaucratic necessity for standardization and consistency, as discussed above. Especially at the appeals levels, however, SSA is under constant judicial pressure to liberalize standards and procedures in accordance with legal, rather than medical or bureaucratic, concepts. SSA continues to resist such efforts, preferring its own interpretations of legislative mandates.
The level of the administrative law judge hearing has drawn the most outside attention (Cofer, 1985, 1987; Mashaw et al., 1978; Parmele, 1987). A central focus has been the appropriate degree of independence of ALJs, who work within SSA's Office of Hearings and Appeals but see themselves as independent. There is a common view within SSA that the ALJs simply "don't follow the rules," that ALJs in particular allow cases without having to justify their decisions the same way that DDS examiners and doctors do. One manager told me that the 50-plus percent reversal rate was a "shameful statistic," and that ALJs as a group, who are "incredibly poorly trained in SSA regulations and medicine," incorrectly "see themselves as members of the judiciary rather than as the administrative personnel they really are."
In contrast to the common SSA view, Cofer (1985) pointed out that ALJs base their decisions on Congressional statutes and judicial precedent rather than on SSA's internal instructions, despite SSA insistence that its own instruction manual presents the correct interpretation. Cofer uncovered several important differences between statutes and SSA guidelines that add to the high reversal rate of DDS denials. Although many ALJs regard the quality of DDS case development as poor, "if the states and ALJs continue to use essentially different standards of judgment, all of the care given to case development will be for naught" (Cofer, 1985, p. 184). This continuing conflict was reflected in a 1983 suit filed by the Association of ALJs against the Secretary of Health and Human Services (HHS) on the grounds that SSA "had directed administrative law judges to ignore court decisions favorable to claimants and had put pressure on them to deny claims" (Liebman, 1985, p. 38).
There are other reasons for the disparity between DDS and ALJ decisionmaking. Perhaps most importantly, Stone (1984) noted, the ALJ sees and talks to the claimant in person, unlike DDS personnel. This allows a focus on the individual's subjective experience rather than on the "average person" approach of the listings. "To 'individualize' a disability determination process in a modern mass society seems incongruous to a bureaucrat; yet a judge will view the bad fortune of an otherwise viable human being" (Cofer, 1985, p. 7). In addition, Stone pointed out that legal and medical notions of causation and proof differ. To oversimplify, the doctor/scientist may allow a claim only if 95 percent certain that the underlying impairment fully causes the inability to work; the lawyer/judge may award benefits if a preponderance, or 50.1 percent, of the evidence shows that the impairment is a contributing cause. Finally, the courts are more likely to interpret the disability program as a contract between the insured and the insurer, a contract "whose provisions are somewhat fuzzy" (Stone, 1984, p. 159) and, thus, to be interpreted liberally, in accordance with public views of disability that are less stringent than the official definition.
Although DDS-ALJ differences are reflected in high overall reversal rates, the conflict is seen even more clearly in cases of mental impairment. After the 1981-82 termination of thousands of disability beneficiaries, appeals to ALJs brought reversal 60 percent of the time. In cases of mental disability, however, the reversal rate was 91 percent (Cofer, 1985, p. 116).
The second relevant aspect of the varying perspectives on disability results from the fact that, although SSA regards the ALJs as too lenient, when ALJs do affirm DDS denials they often are overruled by federal judges who see the ALJs as too tightly linked to SSA. The resulting burden on the courts has led to calls by Supreme Court Justice Antonin Scalia and others to cut down on the "triviality" of federal court cases by establishing specialized Social Security courts (Lauter, 1987). It has also led, not surprisingly, to a large number of private lawyers and nonprofit advocacy groups that provide legal support for claimants who appeal their denials. The National Organization of Social Security Claimants' Representatives publishes a newsletter that informs lawyers of the status of significant legal issues and offers suggestions on how to deal with SSA both in and out of court. Professional legal and advocacy organizations study, and recommend changes in, SSA practices (e.g., "Disability Symposium," 1986; Rubenstein, 1985).
A third related aspect of this general issue is the constant interplay between the courts, which routinely order SSA to modify particular procedures or criteria, and SSA, which often nonacquiesces in rulings with which it disagrees. "The agency complies as to the individual's case but tells its officials, including administrative law judges, to continue applying the policies that reflect the agency's view of the correct legal interpretation" (Liebman, 1985, p. 38). Thus, other claims raising the same issue must each be brought to court individually, adding to the burden on the court, to mutual SSA-ALJ recriminations, and to claimant costs and frustration. When SSA does acquiesce, it often applies the judicial ruling only in the federal district in which the ruling was made, complicating the problem of different DDSs using different rules.
Discussing similar phenomena in the welfare system, Rosenblatt (1982) noted:
The vast majority of decisions are never appealed, not because they are correct, but because the poor lack the information, resources, and advocacy assistance needed to confront the complex welfare bureaucracy. When agency actions are appealed, the resulting decisions do not function as a system of internal control, because no discernible pattern of appellate policy is developed and communicated to the line caseworkers. The result is a system of procedural rights that may help a small number of aggressive or fortunate recipients, but which functions largely as a legitimating symbol of fairness for a generally unchanged system. (pp. 273-274)
Although the appeals levels have forced liberalization of the mental impairment rules, the nature of the process still works against those who do not have the financial resources, stamina, initiative, and forethought that are required to get to court. These qualities remain disproportionately beyond the reach of the mentally disordered.
Suggestions for helping the disabled to better meet their needs can be placed in four categories: (a) improving the present system, which essentially is accepted on its own terms, primarily through greater managerial control; (b) reforming the system administratively or legislatively by altering particular procedures; (c) abandoning some of the system's basic assumptions; and (d) replacing the system.
The usual bureaucratic response to problems such as case inconsistency, employee variability, state discrepancies, and high reversal rates is to attempt to improve the methods it is already using. It is assumed within the agency that failures to meet standards "constitutes a problem of implementation, not problems in the concept of impairment itself. Hence, the SSA responds to criticisms of its determination process . . . by providing more training, more guidelines, and more supervision" (Stone, 1984, p. 127)
Some of these efforts are useful. Better examiner training in mental impairments is clearly in order, if only to reduce examiner confusion and frustration and to enhance job satisfaction. More examiners and clerical assistance would also help. The GAO (1987, 1989b, 1989c) repeatedly reports that employee morale is low across SSA and DDSs, partly because of increased workloads and poor advancement prospects resulting from budget cuts and job freezes and partly because of a sense that management insufficiently considers employee welfare during frequent program changes.
SSA eventually may have to consider dividing examiners into those who work on physical impairment claims and those who work on mental impairments, each with different training and, perhaps, different background requirements. Such a split would be organizationally difficult and would complicate the cases of people with multiple impairments. It would, however, be analogous to the decision, made several years after the SSI program began in 1974, to divide district office claims representatives along program lines because of the increasing inability to master simultaneously the growing complexities of both Social Security and SSI.
Despite efforts to smooth the rough edges, "there are important reasons why a concept of disability based on clinical criteria is bound to fail" (Stone, 1984, p. 127) and why there are limits to the level of accuracy that can be achieved. Attempts to enhance bureaucratic control are often counterproductive. As noted above, enforcing consistency by relying on quantifiable criteria can lower the overall allowance rate (Mashaw, 1983). Interest in devising an objective vocational grid for use in mental impairment cases (Rubenstein, 1985) might be an example of what Hummel (1982) called bureaucracy's "tendency . . . to substitute inner control for outward service" (p. 67).
Many suggestions have been made to reform components of the disability process, and SSA itself has considered a number of different arrangements. Rather than accepting frequent calls to increase judicial review of the bureaucracy by, for example, making hearings more adversarial, SSA has experimented with such innovations as providing for personal contact between DDS examiners and claimants. After one such trial in 1976 resulted in more allowances, SSA recommended implementing this reform throughout the system, but was overruled by HHS (Mashaw, 1983, p. 198). A similar experiment with a Personal Appearance Demonstration Project was mandated by the 1984 Disability Amendments ("Personal Appearance," 1986), and the GAO has continued to advocate face-to-face meetings between examiners and claimants (Delfico, 1991). At the same time, somewhat paradoxically, SSA has experimented with sending an agency representative to hearings. Although officially not designed to make the hearing adversarial, the practice was halted briefly by a federal judge who "found the government representative experiment to be yet another method of tipping the scales against claimants" ("Unconstitutional," 1986, p. 3).
In addition to calling for more examiner-claimant contact, Mashaw (1983) proposed a system that would provide representation for claimants, not by lawyers ("most of whom do not understand the disability system well enough"--pp. 201-202) but, perhaps, by examiners hired specifically to represent claimants. Mashaw would also move away from increased judicial review in favor of a greater professionalization of the decisionmaking process ("a different unhappy compromise"--p. 203). He suggested giving claimants at the reconsideration level an SSA medical examination performed by a panel of three doctors, or, alternatively, leaving decisions to a comprehensive multiprofessional panel of experts. Both of these options would be expensive, and although they would result in more allowances, they would probably not reduce the "irreducible category of marginal claims that will never be consistently decided" (Mashaw, 1983, p. 206).
Another frequently suggested institutional reform is the abandonment of the joint SSA-DDS system in favor of a centralized system directly run by SSA. Studying the prospects of federalization and of another alternative, privatization through contracting out, the GAO (1985) acknowledged that "the statutory definition of disability is necessarily subjective" (p. 10). Either federalization or contracting out would give SSA greater control "and, in theory, offer greater possibilities of increased uniformity" (p. 3), but the GAO concluded that abandoning the present system would meet with much opposition and would probably neither produce better decisions nor save money. The report called, instead, for a number of managerial steps "to improve administration within the current federal/state arrangement; e.g., SSA could improve the directives and guidelines it provides to the DDSs" (p. 4). Of course, if federalization did result in better decisions according to SSA standards, the cost would be a lower allowance rate, especially in states where the DDSs consider national guidelines to be too stringent.
Two broad changes in the basic ideological assumptions upon which SSA is built should be considered, one relating to mental disability in particular, the other more general.
Although the evaluation of claims for physical disability is difficult enough, SSA should explicitly acknowledge that, in contrast to its operating ideology, applying the same kinds of objective criteria to both physical and mental disability is fundamentally misguided. This goes beyond merely acknowledging that the evaluation of mental disability requires more professional judgment than the evaluation of physical disability, and it goes beyond the focus of the new mental listings on functional work-related activity. The new listings, despite their advantages over the old, remain embedded within the medical diagnosis approach, and as such stand opposed to the view that objective medical evaluation intrinsically is incapable of eliminating inequities caused by individual subjectivity and bureaucratic reality. Better training of examiners in how to gather evidence of functional limitations and how to evaluate vocational factors is crucial, but within SSA's operating rationale such vocational analysis remains secondary to the agency psychologist or psychiatrist's rating of medical impairment.
Without doing away with the present approach completely, SSA could strengthen the focus on the claimant's actual ability to function by abandoning the assumption that only a DDS psychiatrist or clinical psychologist can evaluate impairment and that only "medical evidence" provided by an MD or PhD is deemed adequate. Although reports submitted by a claimant's social worker, for example, are now considered by DDS, unless the report is countersigned by a doctor (who may have no continuing interaction with the claimant) the claimant will be required to go to a one-time consultative exam. This insistence on a medical approach prevents the reasonable use of reports submitted by professionals who know the claimant's abilities best. At present, nonmedical reports do affect decisions, but they do not have the weight that they should.
Suggestions have been made to focus more heavily on individualized structured work evaluations in order to better assess vocational capacity (Anthony & Jansen, 1984). While these evaluations are often seen within the agency as potentially useful, they are expensive and time-consuming, and thus rarely used. It is not clear that they add useful information to what is often available from social workers, counselors, and relatives. Of course, as DDSs currently are structured, work evaluation reports are assessed by the psychologist or psychiatrist, and thus do not move away from the medical diagnosis focus. Equally seriously, the objective appearance of such reports masks, but does not change, their subjective nature.
It is not likely that SSA will consider an open abandonment of the medical approach. In fact, it is only since the 1984 Disability Amendments that clinical psychologists have been allowed to evaluate claims without a physician's countersignature (Landers, 1986; Novack, 1987), and it is still too soon to tell how fully they will be integrated into the system. In some DDSs the staff psychologist's job remains primarily the evaluation of psychological test scores--and SSA has suggested reducing the use of psychological tests, a move opposed by APA (Freiberg, 1992). One psychologist told me that agency psychologists, moreso than psychiatrists, find it difficult to rate functional abilities as "markedly" or "moderately" limited, to place claimants in narrow categories. This point is in keeping with speculation about the cognitive effects of training differences between psychologists and psychiatrists (Kingsbury, 1987). Efforts to bring psychologists into SSA on an equal footing with psychiatrists are a step forward for psychology and for claimants, but such efforts may cause psychologists to cling more tightly to the official medical model when the opposite approach is necessary.
Both the mentally and the physically disabled would benefit from the abandonment of another fundamental SSA assumption: the insistence that the definition of disability should take place divorced from the realities of the job market. Although there has been some minor erosion of this ideological view, particularly for older workers, much more needs to be done. As is the case in Western Europe, the definition of disability should take into account the reasonable chances that an impaired person will actually be able to find a job when competing for scarce openings with unimpaired individuals. It is grossly unreasonable to deny benefits to someone who might be able to do some kind of limited work but who will never be hired. This basic policy decision disproportionately disadvantages the mentally disordered, who must deal not only with their impairment but also with the accompanying stigma that makes finding work even more unlikely.
Merely broadening the definition of disability, which necessarily is arbitrary to begin with, can be done within the existing SSA framework. A more far-reaching approach would be to rethink the whole basis for separate disability, unemployment, welfare, and even tort systems (see Abraham & Liebman's, 1993, discussion of "the gaps and overlaps in the existing network of compensation institutions"--p. 77). In a society where there are more people than jobs and where problems of distribution rather than of production interfere with providing basic needs for all, it is not enough to tinker with individual components of the present bureaucratic structure.
Of course, completely doing away with the disability bureaucracy, perhaps by instituting a negative income tax that would guarantee a minimal standard of living, would not be without bureaucratic problems (Mashaw, 1983, pp. 183-185) and is unlikely to be considered seriously in an economically conservative era. Also unlikely in the near future are other progressive developments that would help the partially disabled find appropriate jobs. Because "virtually everyone is capable of doing something productive" (Taibi, 1990, p. 919), the institution of a shorter work week, the creation of meaningful parttime work at higher wages and benefits, and the transition to more cooperative workplaces and more liveable communities might allow many people currently seen as disabled to participate more actively in the society around them. The potential benefits of fundamental social change should not be dismissed solely because such change is not imminent. The degree to which centralized bureaucratic reality is inherently at odds with meeting human needs requires us at least to consider solutions that ultimately go beyond minor reforms (Fox, 1985, 1993; Wineman, 1984).
In the meantime, and without losing sight of broader efforts at change, reforms of SSA's current approach to disability evaluation must continue. The methods used to adjudicate claims for physical disability remain complex and controversial. They are applied inconsistently and are only marginally justified at best. The complexity and inconsistency are increased many times over, and the justification decreased by a similar degree if not lost entirely, when methods based on the same assumptions are used to adjudicate claims for mental disability.
Before the new mental listings went into effect, Rubenstein (1985) noted that "the changes in the standards and procedures . . . are almost complete. They amount to a major and beneficial overhaul. Yet, because of bureaucratic resistance to change, the practical consequences cannot be foreseen" (pp. 722-723). Since then, the consequences support my suspicion that the mismatch between bureaucratic reality and the fundamental nature of mental disorder, even in the conceivable absence of explicit bureaucratic resistance, sharply limits the potentially beneficial impact of the new listings or of any similar reforms. As long as there is a continuation of the "medicalization of social problems" (Stone, 1984, p. 12) and the approach to meeting basic needs remains based on objective medical decisionmaking, mentally disordered people will remain disproportionately disadvantaged.
Abraham, K. S., & Liebman, L. (1993). Private insurance, social insurance, and tort reform: Toward a new vision of compensation for illness and injury. Columbia Law Review, 93, 75-118.
Achenbaum, W. A. (1986). Social Security: Visions and revisions. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Anthony, W. A., & Jansen, M. A. (1984). Predicting the vocational capacity of the chronically mentally ill. American Psychologist, 39, 537-544.
Bloch, F. S. (1992). Disability determination: The Administrative process and the role of medical personnel. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.
Buck, J. A. (1982). Should mental health services be structured like medical care? Inquiry, 19, 211-221.
Cates, J. R. (1983). Insuring inequality: Administrative leadership in Social Security, 1935-54. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Cofer, D. P. (1985). Judges, bureaucrats, and the question of independence: A study of the Social Security Administration hearing process. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.
Cofer, D. P. (1987). Bureaucratic efficiency vs. bureaucratic justice: Administrative law judges in the Social Security Administration. Judicature, 71, 29-35.
Collins, K. P., & Erfle, A. (1985). Social Security Disability Benefits Reform Act of 1984: Legislative history and summary of provisions. Social Security Bulletin, 48(4), 5-32.
Delfico, J. F. (1990). Social Security: Employment and health status of Social Security denied applicants (Report of Testimony No. GAO/T-HRD-90-48). Washington, DC: General Accounting Office.
Delfico, J. F. (1991). Social Security: Reforms in the disability determination and appeals process (Report of Testimony No. GAO/T-HRD-91-24). Washington, DC: General Accounting Office.
Delfico, J. F. (1992). Social Security disability: Growing funding and administrative problems (Report of Testimony No. GAO/T-HRD-92-28). Washington, DC: General Accounting Office.
Derthick, M. (1979). Policymaking for Social Security. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Derthick, M. (1990). Agency under stress: The Social Security Administration in American government. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Diehl, M. (1990). Screening out worthy Social Security disability claimants and its effect on homelessness. University of Miami Law Review, 45, 617-650.
Disability symposium. (1986, May). Social Security Forum, pp. 1, 3.
Dixon, R. G. (1973). Social Security Disability and mass justice. New York: Praeger.
Fox, D. R. (1985). Psychology, ideology, utopia, and the commons. American Psychologist, 40, 48-58.
Fox, D. R. (1991). Social science's limited role in resolving psycholegal social problems. Journal of Offender Rehabilitation, 17, 159-166.
Fox, D. R. (1993). Psychological jurisprudence and radical social change. American Psychologist, 48, 234-241.
Fox, D. R. (1994). Governmental Ideology and Bureaucratic Reality in Mental Disability Evaluation. [This unpublished manuscript]
Freiberg, P. (1992, July). SSA may postpone rules announcement. APA Monitor, p. 24.
General Accounting Office. (1985). Current status of the federal/state arrangement for administering the Social Security disability programs (Report No. GAO/HRD-85-71). Washington, DC: Author.
General Accounting Office. (1986). Implementation of new mental impairment criteria for disability benefits (Report No. GAO/HRD-86-75BR). Washington, DC: Author.
General Accounting Office. (1987). Social Security Administration: Stable leadership and better management needed to improve effectiveness (Report No. GAO/HRD-87-39). Washington, DC: Author.
General Accounting Office. (1989a). Social Security: Selective face-to-face interviews with disability claimants could reduce appeals (Report No. GAO/HRD-89-22). Washington, DC: Author.
General Accounting Office. (1989b). Social Security: Staff reductions and service quality (Report No. GAO/HRD-89-106BR). Washington, DC: Author.
General Accounting Office. (1989c). Social Security: Views of agency personnel on service quality and staff reductions (Report No. GAO/HRD-89-37BR). Washington, DC: Author.
Hummel, R. P. (1982). The bureaucratic experience (2nd ed.). New York: St. Martin's Press.
Jansen, M. A. (1986). Mental health policy: Observations from Europe. American Psychologist, 41, 1273-1278.
Kingsbury, S. J. (1987). Cognitive differences between clinical psychologists and psychiatrists. American Psychologist, 42, 152-156.
Landers, S. (1986, October). Social Security issues call for help. APA Monitor, p. 36.
Lauter, D. (1987, March 2). Administration stand key for Scalia's reforms. National Law Journal, pp. 5, 41.
Liebman, L. (1976). The definition of disability in Social Security and Supplemental Security Income: Drawing the boundaries of social welfare estates. Harvard Law Review, 89, 833-867.
Liebman, L. (1985). Disability appeals in Social Security programs. Washington, DC: Federal Judicial Center.
Lipton, F. R., Sabatini, A., & Katz, S. E. (1983). Down and out in the city: The homeless mentally ill. Hospital and Community Psychiatry, 34, 817-821.
Mashaw, J. L. (1983). Bureaucratic justice: Managing Social Security disability claims. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Mashaw, J. L., Goetz, C.J., Goodman, F. I., Schwartz, W. F., Verkuil, P. R., & Carrow, M. M. (1978). Social Security hearings and appeals: A study of the Social Security Administration hearing system. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books.
Meyer, C. W., & Wolff, N. (1993). Social Security and individual equity: Evolving standards of equity and adequacy. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.
Mezey, S. G. (1988). No longer disabled: The federal courts and the politics of social security disability. New York: Greenwood Press.
Mills, L. G. (1993). A calculus for bias: How malingering females and dependent housewives fare in the Social Security Disability system. Harvard Women's Law Journal, 16, 211-232.
Novack, T. A. (1987). Update on Social Security disability determination for the mentally impaired. Professional Psychology: Research and Practice, 18, 265-268.
Novack, T. A., & Bernard, J. L. (1985). Disability determination for the mentally impaired: Conflicts and changes. Professional Psychology: Research and Practice, 16, 148-158.
Office of Assessment. (1987, March). Impact of the revised listings for mental disorders: Fiscal Year 1986 and July-December 1986. Baltimore: Social Security Adminstration.
Parmele, P. (1987). Preserving the judicial independence of federal administrative law judges: Are existing protections sufficient? Journal of Law and Politics, 4, 207-232.
Personal Appearance Demonstration Projects. (1986, January). Social Security Forum, pp. 3-5.
Reno, V. P., & Price, D. N. (1985). Relationship between the retirement, disability, and unemployment insurance programs: The U.S. experience. Social Security Bulletin, 48(5), 24-37.
Rosenblatt, R. E. (1982). Legal entitlement and welfare benefits. In D. Kairy (Ed.), The politics of law: A progressive critique (pp. 262-278). New York: Pantheon Books.
Rubenstein, L. S. (1985). SSA issues new rules governing mental impairment claims. Clearinghouse Review, 19, 715-723.
Rubenstein, L. S. (1986). Access to treatment and rehabilitation for severely mentally ill poor people. Clearinghouse Review, 20, 382-391.
Social Security Act, § 223 (d), 20 C.F.R. § 404.1505 (1992).
State agencies' workloads protested. (1987, February). Social Security Forum, pp. 1,3.
Stone, D. A. (1984). The disabled state. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Stuve, P. (1986). Barriers to services for the CMI in the Social Security system. Unpublished manuscript.
Szasz, T. S. (1974). The myth of mental illness. New York: Harper & Row.
Taibi, A. (1990). Politics and due process: The rhetoric of Social Security disability law. Duke Law Journal, 1990, 913-966.
Title II, Title XVI and Concurrent Title II and XVI decisions for disability claims by workers, widows, widowers and dependent adult children. (1986, April). Social Security Forum, p. 7.
Tringo, J. L. (1970). The hierarchy of preference toward disability groups. Journal of Special Education, 4, 295-306.
Unconstitutional: Government Representative Program enjoined. (1986, July). Social Security Forum, pp. 1, 3-5.
Weaver, C. L. (1989). Social Security disability policy in the 1980s and beyond. In M. Berkowitz & M. A. Hill (Eds.), Disability and the labor market. Ithaca, NY: ILR Press.
Wineman, S. (1984). The politics of human services: Radical alternatives to the welfare state. Boston: South End Press.
|
personal/political observations |
|||||||
|
|
some political, most not |
Page
updated
August 5, 2009
|